|
The
Physics of the Antichrist,
a Theory of Everything, VI of VI:
Social Laws of Nature, Coming and Going
Don’t Forget Yourself
Among the childhood picture books that I recall with particular clarity
tells a story about some brothers — eight, I think — on a
fishing excursion. Upon their return to shore, each brother performs a
headcount, and each comes up with only seven. As they mourn the loss of
one of their brethren, a person wanders by, asks what is the matter, and
counts eight of them. Each had forgotten to include himself.
This story is, in the essential human tendency that it seeks to highlight,
related to Frank Tipler’s failure to incorporate the present, the
period of movement from the beginning to the end of time, in the model
of God that he proposes in The Physics of Immortality. The principle
certainly carries through to the problem of scientists’ excluding
first-person experience in their models. The self is so obvious that we
take it for granted and forget to include it.
The self, in this sense, includes not only our persons and our daily
lives, but our entire way of experiencing the universe. When a model of
reality almost explicitly excludes this central aspect, it necessarily
becomes increasingly complex. Ultimately, when the concept of experience
is brought back into play, the result is a surreal impression. Life doesn’t
feel like a model.
Yet, once we’ve overcome that surreal reaction and sought to align
the model with regular ol’ existence, the entire thing seems a bit
too obvious and humdrum to capture anything significant. What had begun
to seem like a portrait of a new and distant land has turned out merely
to be a description of our own backyard. How could it be otherwise? We’ve
never left the comfort of the patio, after all.
Seeing into Daisy’s Eyes
Many years after I’d read of the resolution to the fishing brothers’
problem, a high school English teacher handed me a copy of The Great
Gatsby with the original cover. Several classes passed in discussion
of the text before somebody pointed out that the eyes on the cover had
naked women in their irises. I recall reaching for my book to justify
my incredulity and noticing that the other student’s observation
was, in fact, true. The rest of the period was lost on me, as I spent
it staring at the cover trying to figure out how I had missed something
that was now so obvious.
I propose that, in a meaningful sense, I had been living in a world in
which there were no bodies on the cover of The Great Gatsby. Some
would object that the cover had included them all along, and I just didn’t
see them. That’s correct. However, I’m suggesting that, in
a very real and significant way, I might have been living in one of the
infinite Many Worlds in which Francis Cugat had omitted that component
of his cover design.
As odd as that may sound, it isn’t but so original a suggestion.
Some have put forward the proposition, keeping with the same example,
that not only did I live in a world in which the cover was different,
but also that it would be more true to say that Francis Cugat didn’t
exist until I looked up his name just now. Even beyond the dangerous solipsism
of such a suggestion, it sets up an implausibly erratic view of Many Worlds,
with people — even planets — popping into and out of existence.
In the model described in the previous essays of this series, each adjacent
world is only minimally different from the next. And since everybody alive
exists in each world in which they are possible, it would represent an
impossible leap to reach worlds that were so significantly different.
One implication of the mesh model of Many Worlds is that we can reconverge
with particular strains of reality that we had previously left; I could
move back toward a world in which the naked women were not on the cover
of The Great Gatsby. However, we cannot undo our experience,
and I have thought about having not seen the bodies and have mentioned
it to others, thereby moving farther and farther into the range of worlds
in which the cover is as I now believe it to be. To move away from that
position would involve, first, believing that the cover must have been
subsequently changed and, then, believing that I’d just imagined
the whole thing.
An essential rule, in this respect, is that our lives are progressive
— moving forward in time. However, if time travel were possible
the mesh model would easily dispense with all questions involving the
meetings of multiple “yous”; you would probably inhabit the
body of you at the particular time to which you’d traveled. Regardless,
at present, our control over time seems largely to do with the speed of
its passage, something that might be related to the number of worlds through
which we move with or without conscious deliberation.
A second essential rule is that our movement across worlds must be observationally
continuous; each moment must logically follow from the previous. Theoretically,
if somebody had complete information about all of the laws of nature,
your physiological makeup, and all input — cultural and physical
— that you could possibly experience, he could plot out everything
that you could possibly do. This does not mean that a person with even
total information about you could do more than guess at what you would
do.
Several physicists have, over the past decade and a half, put forward
an experiment to test the Many Worlds Interpretation against alternatives.
Essentially, it uses the scientist for the Schrodinger’s cat and
proposes that, if the scientist never dies despite repeated runs of an
experiment that gives him a fifty percent chance of survival, then there
must be multiple universes. The scientist can only observe the one in
which he lives. As with the definition of a person by that person’s
“pattern,” the thought experiment is unsatisfactory. In a
continuously branching Many Worlds Interpretation, why should it be that
the scientist’s awareness will forever follow the path in which
he survives? This seems to presume some form of soul, and an immortal
soul need not avoid bodily death to remain immortal.
However, because soul is rejected at the very beginning of the scientific
examination, the “quantum suicide” thesis has expanded to
the “quantum immortality” thesis, which suggests that the
first-person observer can never die. Of course, although I accept this
immortality within a Christian context, it isn’t logically possible
for a human body to exist forever, which is the immortality intended by
the philosopher physicists. Immortality in their meaning essentially gives
a human the ability, or the natural tendency, to “choose”
a world in which he survives. If our experience is really a progression
through possible instances of time, then we will eventually become “trapped”
in fatal events.
If we reject the completely solipsistic view that one’s personal
reality is all that matters, then it is certain that other people, or
merely chance, put us in situations in which survival simply isn’t
a reality that our souls can choose. Consider two people heading toward
each other in a particular region of the Many Worlds, with a man about
to run over a woman accidentally with his car. Once the car is bearing
down on the woman, it is too late for her survival to be a matter of her
choice. She cannot jump in time, and she cannot move to worlds that are
not connected to the one in which she exists.
The only way she could deliberately choose to avoid the accident would
be if she had some foreknowledge or suspicion about the event. In that
way, she could arrange not to be in that spot at that time, or alternatively,
she could somehow prevent the man from playing his role in her death.
Even for those who don’t believe in premonitions, the procedure
through which the woman avoids her death seems obvious. And that’s
the point: reality is as we experience it to be.
Soul Messages
Of course, different people experience reality in different ways, which
makes sense if people are, indeed, inhabiting different realities. This
divergence, in my view, is the nugget of truth on which the various forms
of relativism are built. However, while relativists are correct that everybody’s
reality is equally real, they err in presuming that this means
that all realities are equally valid or true.
The line between solipsism (only my reality is true) and multiplicity
(every reality is equally true) has proven to be a difficult one to walk
for those who ponder the intersection of physics and philosophy. In the
former case, the tendency is to suggest that the individual exists in
the most true world by definition, sometimes with the suggestion that
he or she is the decisive personality for the universe. In the latter
case, the tendency is to see every version of an individual as equally
valid, existing in self-contained realities that can’t be compared
judgmentally.
Those who have chosen to reject the notion that the physical world exists
entirely inside the individual’s mind, and who take an essentially
materialistic view of reality, have had to reconcile two beliefs. The
first is the assumption that the mind and experience result from the workings
of our bodies and surroundings (our minds supervene on, or follow
from, our bodies). The second relates to the observation that we interact
with each other and our desire for those interactions to be real.
If the mind supervenes on the brain, then each of the Many Worlds could
only correspond to a single mind. Thus, when the world splits, your mind
moves to only one of the possibilities according to your belief about
what happened. However, if somebody else believes differently than you,
then that person’s mind must move to a different world. Therefore,
the version of that person with whom you thereafter interact is a “mindless
hulk.” To resolve this melancholy outcome, philosophers have proposed
a “many-minds interpretation,” in which every version of us
has its own mind, which may or may not communicate in some way with our
other minds and/or with the many minds of other people.
In this area of thought, the mesh model of Many Worlds would fall somewhere
between a “single-mind interpretation” and a “many-minds
interpretation” because, in it, each of us has a single soul (or
mind), yet that soul could reach and “be present in” every
iteration of our bodies. The world is as a person believes it to be, so
one cannot hold different beliefs about the same physical state; rather,
belief — the disposition of the soul — dictates which physical
world one inhabits. As the Eucharist reminds us, the universe has a lower-level
implementation that is spiritual and exists along with the physical level
as one reality.
If, as implied in a previous essay in this series, the Eucharist can
act as a beacon guiding us to the correct path through the Many Worlds,
fading but still reaching us as we move away from the Son, then the “mindless
hulk” problem dissipates. We aren’t always interacting with
ensouled people as we work our way through life, but this admission is
only objectionable if one insists on seeing the world as in continuous
motion — transforming, rather than stepping, from one state to another.
With each world being just a momentary state, and your soul moving through
imprints of you from moment to moment, your multiple physical manifestations
are essentially connected. They’re faces of a single identity: you.
Attributing this perspective to other people, while a given person’s
soul may not be present in the specific version with whom you’re
interacting, it makes no sense to see that version as “mindless.”
After all, it would be harsh to label somebody as a mindless hulk just
because he was daydreaming and not paying attention to you.
The practical implication of this model is that, when we argue and can’t
resolve the difference, the person really is living on a different track
of reality — perhaps not the right one. Although I characterize
our perception as points on the spectrum-like playing board of the many
world, we can think of our souls emanating out from that point. This would
be how we persuade others to move toward us — by seeking to enfold
them in such a way as to direct them toward the concentrated points of
our souls lie. It may be that this is no more than what we might call
“sincerity,” or perhaps it is seen in the strength of emotion
conveyed.
Through the Looking Glass
In summary, the mesh model of Many Worlds holds that an imprint of a
person exists in every world and in every position that he can take, given
the laws of physics, his biological make-up, and the location and circumstances
into which he was born. The individual soul, observable as continuous
experience, takes logically consistent steps through this mesh of possibilities,
moving progressively through time. As the person travels through time,
he can sense the positions of other souls — the most prominent of
which is God. Moreover, people can communicate with each other in ways
that transcend language and take cues from each other about what is important,
or even what is real.
This framework for life would obviously have implications for childhood
development. For one thing, it proffers a formulation of the nature versus
nurture distinction. For another, it highlights the importance of stability
and emotional connection with parents — preferably two parents,
who give their child more than one reference point (which diverge, at
the very least, based on the different worlds made likely according to
gender).
It would be romantic to believe that two people’s souls must connect
in order for them to conceive, but it is more plausible that only the
mother’s is required (which is not to say that presence of soul
guarantees conception). It could be the case that a child’s soul
travels along with the mother’s during pregnancy. After birth, the
child begins to have more options according to the world’s input.
This is the point at which a father’s presence is beneficial —
crucial — for the child’s wellbeing. If we consider that the
Eucharist is a sacrament, then it seems reasonable to suggest that sacramental
marriage would work on the level of soul in some way, as well. Perhaps
it serves to call the spouses’ souls toward the same range of worlds.
If this were the mechanism, then it would still be possible, although
less certain, for people to maintain relationships that duplicate marriage
with respect to their souls and the benefits to their children.
As for the children for whom a couple is “fated,” the chances
that the same parents could conceive the same child in significantly different
worlds are slim; even just a shift of a few variables would result in
a different sperm meeting a different egg. Regardless, versions of us
who differ dramatically in origin would be very difficult to reach because
the belief in our parents is pretty central, and we would emotionally
avoid options that moved beyond some core matters of identity.
Whatever the familial particulars, it is indubitable that the society
in which one lives imparts guidelines for what is to be considered reality.
This is how the idea that social and cultural factors are akin to laws
of nature fits into the mesh model; like the laws of physics, they determine
what states of being are possible, although social boundaries lean more
toward probability than do natural ones. Including the “law”
that we look to each other for cues of what is real, the foundation for
claims of relativism becomes apparent. Mass delusion exists when many
souls convince each other that they are on the right track, which presents
us with a sticky problem through which to work in our lifetimes.
On an individual basis, what we see as insanity would result from choosing
to move to worlds that are outliers in the general consensus. The world
of the lunatic is equally real, but it is isolated from the community
of souls. Increasingly so, until he or she moves beyond where it is even
logically possible for certain other people to exist, because their genetic
makeup and individual circumstances would have determined closer horizons.
It is an interesting question whether one could go so far beyond the
norm — become so crazy — as to move to worlds in which they
could actually do the impossible. My inclination is to say that it is
unlikely, since they would still be bounded by the laws of physics. However,
the point is almost moot since, in the range of worlds in which everybody
else lives, the impossible act wouldn’t occur.
Another interesting question is whether historical events can lead to
diverged clusters of soul-inhabited realities. I think of this in relation
to an historical anecdote from high school history class. During the European/American
conquest of North America, a shaman of a native tribe blessed some reed
vests and declared that they would stop bullets. Of course, in our history
books, the bullets proved stronger than the magic. But could those Indians’
souls have followed a path in which, whether by magic or luck, the trick
worked? I would offer a tentative affirmative, but with the options that
the group would either have been killed at some other event on the periphery
of the range of worlds that we now inhabit, or they would have moved off
in paths that it would be nigh impossible for you or me to reach.
“Well, Duh!” Metaphysically Speaking
This entire endeavor may very well seem odd from multiple directions.
The idea that there is a heretofore largely unexplored “level”
of experienced reality, which gives continuity to a moving picture universe
that flickers from one complete world to the next can certainly evoke
surreal impressions. In that respect, the theory will be disclaimed because
life doesn’t feel that way. In the other direction, from
a scientific point of view, it will be attacked because life isn’t
measurably that way.
Both criticisms are correct.
The difference between the two reactions has to do with basic strategies
for understanding the world. One side believes only what can be proven;
the other believes based on intuition. In these essays, I’m talking
about the point of intersection between observable reality and experiential
reality. This entire theory represents a mere model to connect reality
as it feels to reality as it is observed. It is an abstract model, and
as such, it loses the experience of the thing. Life is a matter of experience,
not of comprehension.
When I started to think about ways to test my proposals, I considered
an experiment in which a person decided to believe differently about something
important and devoted maximum effort to coming to believe it. If it became
true, that would provide some indication that the world in which the person
lived had actually changed. There are two problems with this experiment.
First, there are too many variables, deriving both with the subject and
the observer. Human beings are chronically unwilling to honestly change
their minds, except by accident. Therefore, it would be impossible for
the subject to be sure, even him or herself, that the outcome wasn’t
“tainted”; obviously, if one believes something important
to be true, convincing oneself otherwise is difficult indeed. Moreover,
the observer inherently lives in a different world from the subject and,
therefore, would be unable to tell that a fundamental belief had changed.
Second, these changes happen over time, and we are bound by the rules
of our existence. As the subject looked into reasons that the desired
belief might be true, he or she would simply believe that it was, in fact,
true. Perhaps this point would be better illustrated if the hypothetical
experiment centered around circumstances rather than beliefs. Suppose
you decide that you want to test the mesh model of Many Worlds by willing
your soul to move toward a version of you who is a millionaire. The conclusion
of my theory is that, if it is logically possible for you to do so given
your current circumstances and traits, you can become a millionaire by
making the right decisions according to the laws of physics and the society
within which you live. Well, of course.
This “difficulty of the obvious” would almost definitely
arise with any theory that seeks to describe reality accurately and in
totality. Some philosophers and physicists seem to get caught up in their
equations and their jargon and to lose sight of what it is they’re
seeking to model. Perhaps they believe the complexity to be necessary
in order to excise sensed knowledge or revelation. Unfortunately, one
cannot describe reality without acknowledging the central truth about
it: it is felt. Experience is in every way greater and more important
than models.
By the same token, however, those who privilege experience, feeling,
and faith require a model because the secular ideal will not accept those
forms of knowledge without a rational justification. All of the components
of this “theory of everything,” with the exception of the
explicitly Christian components, can be expressed in terms of psychology,
sociology, or other secular formulations for intangibles. However, even
that might not satisfy physical scientists who recoil even from the encroachment
of supposed “social scientists” into their territory.
For such people, even without the religious associations, this theory
would likely seem too obvious and simple to resolve such highfalutin problems
as Many Worlds. I think scientists, as a group, have gotten so used to
discovering new things, the new worlds of ever-smaller and ever-larger
reality, that it would naturally evade them that what they are describing
is something so obvious to any first-person observer. It’s fascinating
to think of multiple realities all existing in parallel. It’s somehow
more mundane to see them all as merely the possible moments in the realities
that we all experience every day. And perhaps it has the feeling of ceding
turf for scientists to admit social science, the arts, and (most especially)
religion into important roles in the functioning of the universe.
Between Two Gods
In Romans 12:2, St. Paul exhorts the reader, “Do not conform any
longer to the pattern of this world, but be transformed by the renewing
of your mind. Then you will be able to test and approve what God’s
will is — his good, pleasing and perfect will.” Although this
translation, from the New International Version, is unique in
the extent to which it does so, this passage is applicable to the ideas
that I’ve presented throughout this series of essays. Whether it
is the “pattern of this world” or merely “this age”
to which we must not conform, it is through transformation and renewal
of the mind that we align ourselves with God’s path through the
history of the universe.
Tipler is absolutely correct, in his physics-only sense, to confirm the
shared identity of emulations, of the patterns, because each could
be inhabited by the soul of the person. We must offer our bodies
as sacrifices (Romans 12:1), concentrating on the direction of our souls.
With souls bouncing from one world to another throughout time, it is a
puzzle that, according to my theory (and accepting Tipler’s), the
universe near the Omega Point will be entirely soul-less.
As I’ve previously written, the Omega Point would be God creating
Himself on our level of implementation, like a divine story writing itself
into a book. But we must not concentrate too much on the mechanism by
which that story would be written. My greatest offense at Tipler’s
theory was the implication that life, “the biosphere,” would
create or become the Omega Point. This cannot be the
case.
The eternity, the immortality, of Tipler’s Heaven becomes possible
because time extends to infinity. The inhabitants of the universe must
make it collapse in such a way as to ensure that it is in the process
of collapsing forever. It never reaches the point of its end, the singularity.
Even in that future time, we would only be moving toward God,
eventually with the decreases in distance becoming so minute as to make
the “lines” appear parallel.
The Heaven of the Omega Point, it is important to remember, exists at
a higher level of implementation. The “computer” itself exists
at the level of reality that we currently experience, and our emulations
would be run on it. Thus, if we take our souls to be written in the emotional
face of reality, and if we imagine those souls one day claiming their
rightful patterns within the Omega Point, then perhaps this is God’s
method of tying His creation of Himself, the Omega Point, to Himself.
Our souls, in this scenario, are not necessary for the creation of the
Omega Point — indeed, they contradict its development — but
they are necessary in order to connect it to God.
This concept of connection is critical. It is how God guides us to the
proper world. It is how we reach out to each other as we move through
the mesh of the Many Worlds in what would otherwise be a lonely, solitary
journey. And perhaps it is this connection across worlds — through
Love — that was the catalyst for Jesus’ Resurrection and,
if Tipler is correct, the quantum tunneling that made it possible. In
the end, when all the science has been applied and digested and made to
conform with our experience of reality, the lesson is one that
should surprise no Christian: the universe was created for the purpose
of Love. And we were created to be God’s expression of love for
His creation.
Now the dwelling of God is with men, and he will live with them. They
will be his people, and God himself will be with them and be their God.
(Revelation 21:3)
Tipler, Frank J. The Physics
of Immortality (Anchor Books, 1994)
|